What Wiki Doesn’t Know About Me
In 1976, when I delivered the John Locke Lectures
at Oxford, I often spent time with Peter Strawson, and one day at lunch he made
a remark I have never been able to forget. He said, "Surely half the
pleasure of life is sardonic comment on the passing show". This blog
is devoted to comments, not all of them sardonic, on the passing philosophical
show.
Hilary Putnam
Although I have great respect for
what Wikipedia has achieved, I am disappointed that the description of my views
in the article about me is one that could well have been written in 1999,
when I published The Threefold Cord; Mind, Body and World. Here is “wiki’s” current
description:
‘In metaphysics,
he originally espoused a position called metaphysical
realism, but eventually
became one of its most outspoken critics, first adopting a view he called
"internal realism”, which he later abandoned in favor of a pragmatist-inspired direct realism.
Putnam's "direct realism" aims to return the study of metaphysics to
the way people actually experience the world, rejecting the idea of mental
representations, sense data,
and other intermediaries between mind and world. In his later work, Putnam
has become increasingly interested in American pragmatism, Jewish philosophy,
and ethics, thus engaging with
a wider array of philosophical traditions. He has also displayed an interest
in metaphilosophy,
seeking to "renew philosophy" from what he identifies as narrow and
inflated concerns.’
More detail is given in the body
of the wiki article, but the sections titled Metaphysics and Ontology and Pragmatism
and Wittgenstein are very similar to the foregoing. This would have been
pretty good if published in 2000 (although the suggestion that “direct realism”
was my whole metaphysical position, and not simply my view in the philosophy of
perception is very strange). but what it obviously misses is the many papers I
published in the next decade and a half. Since 2012, when 36 of those papers
were published by Harvard under the title Philosophy
in an Age of Science, there does not seem to be any excuse for not doing a
substantial revision. Here are some
things I would like to see recognized in a revised and improved version of my
entry:
“Direct realism” and “commonsense
realism”
In The Threefold
Cord, I defended “direct realism” with respect to perception (although I
always put that term in “raised-eyebrow quotes” to indicate it was an
old-fashioned term; I mostly spoke of “natural realism” and “commonsense
realism” without the raised-eyebrow quotes). But the last of these terms,
“commonsense realism” comprised much more than direct realism with respect to perception: it also comprised
commonsense realism with respect to conception,
by which I meant the “naïve realist” view that when we think of something we do not
observe (e.g. deer on a meadow when no human is present, or even subatomic
particles) our thought genuinely relates to the deer or the particles, and not
to mental representations. (The Threefold
Cord, pp. 43-64)
More recently, however, in the final chapter of Philosophy in an Age of Science (as well
as in “Reply to Ned
Block.” Reading Putnam, ed. M.
Baghramian (London: Routledge, 2013): 319-321), I make it clear that the
rejection of qualia-talk in The Threefold
Cord is something I no longer agree with, and I credit my change of mind
here to Block. The argument in The
Threefold Cord went as follows: (1) I saddled the defender of qualia (aka “sense data”) with the view that
there is no difference between qualia being
identical and their seeming identical.
(esse est percipi, in the case of
qualia.) From this it follows that identity and indistinguishability must be
the same relation. But identity is a transitive relation, and
indistinguishability is not. Conclusion: talk of qualia (or “sense data”)
doesn’t make sense (with a bow to Wittgenstein).
This was all a mistake. In chapter
28, “Wittgenstein a Reappraisal”, of Philosophy
in an Age of Science, I parted ways completely—something I came to
gradually over a period of about six years—with the Wittgensteinian idea that
most philosophical positions and questions don’t make sense. Today, I think that identity and non-identity
of qualia is a question to which brain-science can give answers. We do not have
to rely only on verbal reports. (And if there is some vagueness even in the best scientific criteria, there is
some vagueness in the identity criteria for just about all entities in the natural world!).
Furthermore, this does not mean that
we should return to thinking of qualia as an interface between ourselves and the “external world”. Full perception does not begin with qualia, as traditional empiricism maintained, but with
world-involving transactions. (Chapter 3 of Philosophy
in an Age of Science, “Corresponding With Reality”. On this I agree with
Tyler Burge’s Origins of Objectivity.)
The defense of a modified naïve-realist account of perception does not require
the denial of the existence of qualia. (At present, Hilla Jacobson and I are
writing a book defending this “transactional” view of perception.)
As for mental representations, here
too, it is true that representing external things is not merely having mental pictures or “sentences in Mentalese” that are caused by those things: it is exercising
psychological capacities that enable
one represent things and features of things; but just as qualia do have a role
to play in perception, even if it is not the role that traditional empiricism
assigned to them, so mental representations do have a role to play in conception,
even if, here too, traditional empiricism led us astray for several centuries.
I regret the “Wittgensteinian” tone with which I sneered at talk of “mental
representations”.
In Corresponding With Reality” I
described my present position as “liberal functionalist”, and I explained the
term thus:
What I have
in mind in speaking of a “liberal functionalist” is someone who, like me (or
like me today), accepts the basic functionalist idea that what matters for
consciousness and for mental properties generally is the right sort of functional capacities and not the
particular matter that subserves those capacities, but (1) does not insist that
those functions be “internal”, that is, completely describable without going
outside the organism’s “brain” [thus Gibsonian “affordances” and Millikan’s
“normal biological functioning” in an environment can all be involved in the
description of the “functional organization” of an organism]; (2) does not
insist that those capacities be described as capacities to compute (although she is naturally happy
when computer science sheds light on some part of our functioning); and (3)
does not even eschew intentional idioms, if they are needed, in describing our
functioning, although she naturally wants an account of how intentional
capacities grow out of proto-intentional capacities in our evolutionary
history.
The first
of these three characteristics of my liberalized functionalism implies that the
capacities to function that are relevant to mentality have “long arms”; they
reach out to the environment, as it were, instead of being just the programs of
a computer in the skull. The second characteristic implies that the
psychological, biological and neurological vocabulary needed to describe those
functions and capacities to function need not be described in a vocabulary drawn
from one science (e.g., computer science) or in any way fixed in advance; and
the third characteristic implies that, in particular, intentional idioms (e.g.,
“refers to”) are not taboo. It shouldn’t surprise you that I see the details as largely something to be
worked out by scientists in a number of different fields, but with philosophers
playing the necessary if often unappreciated role of critics and “gadflies”.
I hope WIKI
will one day catch up with all this!