A Response to my Color Anti-realist Friend
In 1976, when I delivered the John Locke Lectures
at Oxford, I often spent time with Peter Strawson, and one day at lunch he made
a remark I have never been able to forget. He said, "Surely half the
pleasure of life is sardonic comment on the passing show". This blog
is devoted to comments, not all of them sardonic, on the passing philosophical
show.
Hilary Putnam
My old friend JW writes:
“I am not clear if you are claiming the ‘greenness’ that I can successfully ascribe through repeated experience of my lawn as colour constancy to be itself a physical property of the object in a particular state (which position teasingly I refer to as ‘farbe an sich’), because elsewhere you recently said that there is no such thing as ‘being' green.
“Or, are you saying that other physical properties
of the object cause me (and most others with my kind of eyes) to see light of
such and such a frequency in such and such a scatter under such and such an
illumination as the same green (more or less) as my lawn was yesterday - given
that it has rained on both days - which is good for the garden in this heat -
even if the look of it is different from morning to evening, from day to day.
This would mean that green objects have the same or similar physical
properties but not necessarily that these properties are in and of themselves
green, just green inducing to my kind of eyes?”
I
want to share my responses to my friend’s questions, so that he and the other
readers of this blog will be clear on what I am saying and what I am not
saying. One thing I did not say was that there is no such thing as being green.
Escher colors again
What
I wrote, in my post of June 11 (“Escher Colors”) - after pointing out that even
for normal viewers there is a slight (but noticeable if one attends to it)
difference between the shade of color an object appears when viewed with the
left eye closed and when viewed either either both eyes open or with the
right eye closed - was:
“Yes,
the question “is the wall (or the sand, in the beach case) really the shade of
gray (or yellow, in the case of the sand) that it appears to be when I use my
right eye or the shade it appears to be when I use both eyes, has no answer,
“makes no sense”—there is no metaphysical fact to the matter to decide this
“question”; but, in another way, it seems to make sense. It
takes reflection, however brief, to convince oneself that there is no such
thing as the wall (or the sand) being colorwise as it looks to my left eye as
opposed to its being as it looks to my right eye. It seems, at least for a moment,
as it something may “really be” that color. But there is
no such thing as that color! The
color, or better the exact shade of gray or yellow or whatever, that
the wall seems to be when I use my right or left eye isn’t the sort of
thing that a color on a paint chart is; the wall could really be, say,
purple-gray32, but there is no such thing as it’s really being
“gray*”, where gray* is the “shade” that the wall “seemed to be” when I used my
left eye to view the wall on that occasion. Subjective colors
are impossible colors. Like an Escher building, they
seem to be real and simultaneously to be impossible. As long I can remember how
the “gray*” wall looked, I can say truly that “it looked gray*”, but “gray*”
occurs intentionally, not referentially, in “looks gray*”; there is such
a thing as “looking gray*” to a person at a time, but no such thing as really
being gray*. Subjective colors aren’t colors; they are Escher colors.
Obviously,
my friend misremembered the claim that there is “no such thing as really being gray*”, not only by
forgetting that it was gray and not green, but my omitting the “*”. There is
such a thing as being gray, but no such thing as being gray*.
But
what is “gray*”? The short answer is
that there is no such thing. The longer answer is that, in “looks gray*”- an
expression I can use to describe a color experience as long as I remember what
that look was[1] - “gray*”
is, in scholastic terminology, syncategoramatic.
It contributes to the meaningful denoting expression “looks gray*” – which denotes
a subjective look – without denoting anything on its own. That’s why there is no such thing as being (to shift
the example) green* but absolutely there is such a thing as being green. Don’t
lose the star!
The importance of distinguishing
colors from color looks
It
seems to me that a major reason that my friend gets me wrong is that, like
Russell, in Problems of Philosophy,
he conflates colors and color looks.
Russell wrote:
“To
make our difficulties plain, let us concentrate attention on the table. To the
eye it is oblong, brown, and shiny, to the touch it is smooth and cool and
hard; when I tap it, it gives out a wooden sound…but as soon as we try to be
more precise our troubles begin. Although I believe that the table is ‘really’
of the same color all over, the parts that reflect the light look much brighter
than the other parts, and some parts look
white because of reflected light. I know that, if I move, the parts that
reflect the light will be different, so that the apparent distribution of
colors on the table will change. It follows that if several people are looking
at the same table at the same moment, no two of them will see exactly the same
different distribution of colors….” (p. 8, 1912 edition)
Here
Russell moves immediately from a difference in “the apparent
distribution of colors”, to “not the same distribution of colors”, that is, he
takes a difference in apparent colors,
or color looks, to be ipso facto a
difference in actual colors. And two pages later Russell writes,
“When,
in ordinary life, we speak of the color of the table, we only mean the sort of
color it will seem to have to a normal spectator from an ordinary point of view
under usual conditions of light. But the other colors which appear under other
conditions have just as good a right to be considered real; and therefore, to
avoid favoritism, we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has any
one particular color.”
In
my Bastille Day post (“The Manifest Image Is Not Wrong”), I wrote that this
sort of view leads to a
wholesale skepticism about the veridicality of what Sellars famously called
“the manifest image. In Russell’s case this “leading to” is immediate. The very
next sentence in Problems of Philosophy
reads: “The shape of the table is no
better. We are all in the habit of judging as to the ‘real’ shapes of things, and
we do this so unreflectingly we come to think that we actually see the real
shapes. But if our table is ‘really’ rectangular, it will look from almost all
points of view as if it had two acute angles and two obtuse angles.” (He makes
similar points about texture, solidity, etc.) And just as he concluded from the
fact that the table has different color
looks when viewed from different positions, that has “no one particular
color”, so he now concludes that “the ‘real’ shape is not what we see” (page
11), and, further down the same page, “The real table, if there is one (sic), is not immediately known to us at all, but must be an inference from what
is immediately know.”
(Since none of the properties of the object
can actually be seen or felt, the “object” becomes an inferred unobservable.)
The answer to the question in my friend’s first
paragraph is that I am saying “the
‘greenness’ that I can successfully ascribe through repeated experience of my
lawn as color constancy to be itself a physical property of the object in a
particular state” and I am also saying (his second paragraph, but I
have intentionally deleted the word “other”) “physical properties of the object
cause me (and most others with my kind of eyes) to see light of such and such a
frequency in such and such a scatter under such and such an illumination as the
same green (more or less) as my lawn was yesterday - given that it has rained
on both days - which is good for the garden in this heat - even if the look of
it is different from morning to evening, from day to day. This would mean
that green objects have the same or similar physical properties” – BUT where he
continues “but not necessarily that these properties are in and of themselves
green, just green inducing to my kind of eyes” I would say that a particular
distribution of those properties (technically, a reflectance profile) is identical with being (physically,
really, green [in hue, neglecting here saturation and brightness]). (That properties can be identical even though
the concepts expressed by the
corresponding predicates are quite different is something I first argued for
and applied to the philosophy of mind in a paper published in 1967[2].)
In sum, I believe that hues are identical with reflectance profiles, and that
this identity is an empirical one, an identity we discover through theory
building and confirmation.
But this would, of course, be absurd, if hues were
identical with subjective looks like gray*. (Russell’s “apparent colors”, which
he later says are in a “private space”).
But they are not. What looks are, and the distinction I draw between
objective looks and subjective looks will be taken up next in this series of
posts.
Epistemology
To close, I need to say a word about my difference
with Russell over epistemology.
[I
discuss these differences in more detail in “Naïve Realism and Qualia”,
forthcoming in Adam Pautz and Daniel Stoljar (eds.) Themes
from Block (MIT)]
Russell takes it that perception starts with sense
data. That is why things in the environment can only be inferences. I take it that we are essentially embodied
creatures, and our knowledge starts with transactions between our bodies,
including our brains and sense organs, and the external environment. Perception
(as Tyler Burge has recently emphasized in his path-breaking book The Origins of Objectivity) involves
representation of objects and features of the environment by perceptual
systems; and our perceptual systems do not begin by examining the organism’s
own qualia. And the properties our perceptual systems represent are not dispositions
to produce qualia. I am a functionalist, but my functionalism today is a
liberal functionalism[3]:
the functional states involved in perception are not computational states, as I
once thought, but object-involving
states, states with “long arms”. If knowledge were something that begins in
“private spaces”, as Russell held, there is no way it would ever get outside!
[1]
In a terminology Ned Block uses, I think in “Wittgenstein and Qualia”, “looks
gray*” is ineffable, meaning by that, not the in principle ineffability that
philosophers rightly view with suspicion, but that there is at present no name
for that look in public language, nor, since it is a purely subjective
look, any way of introducing such a name until we know more about the neural
correlates of the various subjective looks.
[2]
“Psychological
Predicates.” Art, Mind and
Religion, ed.
W. H. Capitan and D. D. Merrill (Pittsburgh, Penn.: University of Pittsburgh
Press, 1967), 37-48. Repr. as “The Nature of Mental States” in Mind, Language and Reality (1975), 429-440.
[3]
For an explanation of the term “liberal functionalism” see chapter 3,
“Corresponding with Reality”, of my Philosophy
in the Age of Science
Love this post. The Sellarsian point that "x looks red" does not mean "x has the power to produce the sensation of red* in ordinary percipients" must (apparently) be made again and again (and again). I only wish you had also made this point in your contribution to the Block book, because I don't think Block has ever quite gotten it himself--and you come off as being on the other side of this divide in that paper.
ReplyDeletecheap swiss copy watches uk, combining elegant style and cutting-edge technology, a variety of styles of cheap ROLEX day-date watches uk, the pointer walks between your exclusive taste style.
ReplyDelete