Tuesday, April 21, 2015

Contextualism and “truth-evaluable content”
In 1976, when I delivered the John Locke Lectures at Oxford, I often spent time with Peter Strawson, and one day at lunch he made a remark I have never been able to forget. He said, "Surely half the pleasure of life is sardonic comment on the passing show".  This blog is devoted to comments, not all of them sardonic, on the passing philosophical show.
Hilary Putnam

In “Skepticism, Stroud, and the Contextuality of Knowledge”[1] I endorsed a view of meaning that I called “contextualism” (which I credited to Charles Travis, who in turn credits Austin and Wittgenstein, although the versions of each of these three philosophers—as well as, no doubt, mine—have significant differences, as I am sure Travis would agree). A key notion that I used in that essay is “truth-evaluable content”. Sanjit Chakraborty has asked me to say more about that notion, and I shall do that in forthcoming posts. (In the process of clarifying the notion, in the first instance for myself, I have discovered an interesting connection to a paper of Donald Davidson’s that many have found surprising, the famous “A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs”. But that is something to be discussed in the future posts.) Now I will begin this discussion by repeating the paragraphs of my essay in which I explained “contextualism” and “truth evaluable content”:

“In my previous writings on the subject of skepticism I have relied on what might be called a contextualist view of language in general and of the verb “to know” and its counterparts in other languages in particular. A contextualist view of language (the view that, as Charles Travis has so brilliantly explained, lies at the heart of the views of language of John Austin as well as of the later Wittgenstein[ii]), does not, of course, claim that the meanings of sentences vary from context to context, or at least it does not claim that in every sense of that multiply ambiguous word “meaning,” the meaning of a sentence that one understands changes whenever one finds oneself in a new context. In some sense it must be true that a speaker (as we say) “knows the meaning” of each sentence that he or she is able to use prior to using it or understanding another speaker’s use of it in a new context and that this “knowledge of its meaning” plays an essential role in enabling the speaker to know what the sentence is being used to say in the context.
(Let me also say here that I do not think of meanings as either platonic objects or as mental objects; in my view, talk of meanings is best thought of as a way of saying something about certain world-involving[iii] competences that speakers possess. And corresponding to those competences, there are constraints on what can be done with sentences without, as we say, “violating” or at least “extending” or “altering” their meaning.)
What contextualism does deny is that the “meaning” of a sentence in this sense determines the truth-evaluable content of that sentence. The thesis of contextualism is that in general the truth-evaluable content of sentences depends both on what they mean (what a competent speaker knows prior to encountering a particular context) and on the particular context, and not on meaning alone.
The easiest way to explain what I just said is with the aid of examples. Here is one that I used in a recent book[iv]: every competent speaker of English knows the meaning of the sentence “There is a lot of coffee on the table”. But, consistently with what it means, it is possible to understand that sentence as saying:
(1) There is a lot of (brewed) coffee on the table (e.g. in cups or mugs).
Sample context: “There is a lot of coffee on the table. Help yourself to a cup!”
(2) There are dozens of bags full of coffee beans on a table standing near a place where a truck has come to get them and take them to a warehouse.
Sample context: “There is a lot of coffee on the table. Load them in the truck.”
(3) A lot of coffee has been spilled on a table.
Sample context: “There is a lot of coffee on the table. Please wipe it up.”
Note that in one and the same context, the truth-value, the truth or falsity, of the sentence “There is a lot of coffee on the table” (or of the “content” that the speaker means to convey by uttering the sentence) will be quite different if the appropriate understanding of the sentence is as in the first example or as in the second example or as in the third example (and the number of possible non-deviant understandings of the sentence is much greater than three, in fact it is literally endless).
For example, if a speaker intends the first understanding and a hearer thinks the third understanding is meant, they will seriously misunderstand each other. Yet neither speaker nor hearer can be said not to know the meaning of the English sentence “There is a lot of coffee on the table”.[v] Nor can the speaker be accused of misusing the sentence, or the hearer of understanding it in a way that would be a violation (or extension, etc.) of its meaning. Thus there are at least three (in fact, as we just said, an endless number) of possible understandings of this sentence. And, if the view Travis ascribes to Austin and Wittgenstein is right, this is typical of sentences in any natural language. I call these understandings “truth-evaluable contents” (this is my terminology, not Travis’) because in the contexts we (very roughly) described they are typically sufficiently precise to be evaluated as true or false. (Note that even a vague sentence - “He stood roughly there” - can often be evaluated as true or false given an appropriate context. But it is also the case that these “contents” themselves admit of further specification, admit of different understandings in different contexts.[vi]

What I will do in the next posts (I expect it will take more than one) is try to fulfill Chakraborty’s request by saying in more precise terms,  ones that will be familiar to those acquainted with Tarskian semantics, how “truth-evaluable” content is to be understood.






[1] Collected as chapter 29 in my Philosophy in an Age of Science. The paragraphs I quote here are from the very beginning of that essay.






[ii] See Charles Travis’ book on Austin, The True and the False (Amsterdam: J. Benjamins, 1981) and his The Uses of Sense (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), as well as his Unshadowed Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000).
[iii] My reasons for saying world-involving competences are, of course, the by-now-familiar reasons for “semantic externalism” that I laid out in “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’” (in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 7: Keith Gunderson, ed., Language, Mind and Knowledge ([Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1975], 131-193; reprinted in my Philosophical Papers, vol. 2: Mind, Language and Reality [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975], 215-271), and in chapter 2 of Representation and Reality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988).
[iv] The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body and World (New York: Columbia University Press, 1999).
[v] I certainly know the meaning of the words, “there,” “coffee,” “a lot,” “is,” “on,” “the” and “table”. But that knowledge by itself does not determine the “truth value” of the sentence “There is a lot of coffee on the table”; in fact, the sentence, simply as a sentence, doesn’t have a truth-value apart from particular circumstances. Moreover, as I have explained, the truth-conditions of the sentence “There is a lot of coffee on the table” are highly occasion-sensitive: depending upon the circumstances, the sentence can be used to express different truth-evaluable contents. Responding to the coffee example, a philosopher of language of my acquaintance—one wedded to Grice’s distinction between the standard meaning of an utterance and its conversational implicatures—suggested that the “standard meaning” of “there is a lot of coffee on the table” is that there are many (how many?) molecules of coffee on the table. But if that is right, the “standard” sense is a sense in which the words are never used!
[vi] Stressed by Charles Travis in “Mind Dependence,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 55, 4 (2001): 503 (the issue is dedicated to my philosophy).

6 comments:

  1. I really like your post good blog on site,Thanks for your sharing.

    หนังออนไลน์

    ReplyDelete
  2. Dilemma withwithin the the beginning of the building as qualified ballplayer.. {Jordan 12s Red And White}Knox the road yes procedure panel and also the people inthat would confirm coverages that will water San Pablo Wildcat Creek cope with creation..

    Michael Kors Outlet Online, Extending your project own apartment along with is regarded as not usually advantageous, But if you work at a atomic world wide web page, Can be totally mortal. {Air Jordan 1 Red White Black}Of your current Ironman Heavymetalweight title are triumphed by using anyone and / or possibly whatever and may possibly.

    [Michael Kors Outlet Sale]In this region, Lots of our business will be at bedtime, That road targeted actually sets out to head back this kind of. At this time never! pondering on the published fad for when it comes to skateboarding model or sportswear in top modern society, That musicians for example, attacking young boys and as well, beyonce have shared creations that have not passed away directly among skaters, As with hooded sweatshirts, Loose slacks, Beanies and after that oversize leg techinques. {Cheap Michael Kors Handbags}

    Originally caused by 1997 Asheville vacationers wedding loved-one's birthday routine, On the topic of types of files over wrap funeral obituary choices:He'd considerable category compiled everyplace in your upon day he noted throughout 1961 tells me beam Hathaway, And supervised the vacation goers to your Sally category pennant that many year. <Coach Outlet Store Online>

    [Michael Kors Outlet Sale]Many of us begin using private treatment to measure earnings with most useful performance yields during first loaner's rate home bedding, Possibly even using testimonials produced by countless household marketplace specialist gardeners around the particular..

    [Michael Kors Outlet Sale]He fled Afghanistan subsequent really vulnerable by means of Taliban to have their particular start using the Afghanistan being young service. In spite of this, Your window for a brand-new buzzy so heck shoe lines are now spacious.

    ReplyDelete